smith moral sentiments 1 sympathy
PartI
Of the propriety of action
Consisting of three sections
Section I Of the sense of propriety
Chapter I Of sympathy
How selfish soever man may be supposed, there are evidently some
principles in his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others,
and render their happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from it except the pleasure of seeing it. Of this kind is pity or
compassion, the emotion which we feel for the misery of others, when
we either see it, or are made to conceive it in a very lively manner.
That we often derive sorrow from the sorrow of others, is a matter of
fact too obvious to require any instances to prove it; for this sentiment,
like all the other original passions of human nature, is by no means
confined to the virtuous and humane, though they perhaps may feel
it with the most exquisite sensibility. The greatest ruffian, the most
hardened violator of the laws of society, is not altogether without it.
As we have no immediate experience of what other men feel, we can
form no idea of the manner in which they are affected, but by conceiving what we ourselves should feel in the like situation. Though our
brother is upon the rack, as long as we ourselves are at our ease, our
senses will never inform us of whathe suffers. They never did, and
never can, carry us beyond our own person, and itis by the imagination only that we can form any conception of what are his sensations.
Neither can that faculty help us to this any other way, than by representing to us what would be our own, if we were in his case. It is
the impressions of our own senses only, not those of his, which our
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
imaginations copy. By the imagination we place ourselves in his situation, we conceive ourselves enduring all the same torments, we enter
as it were into his body, and become in some measure the same person
with him, and thence form some idea of his sensations, and even feel
something which, though weaker in degree, is not altogether unlike
them. His agonies, when they are thus brought home to ourselves,
when we have thus adopted and made them our own, begin at last to
affect us, and we then tremble and shudder at the thought of what
he feels. For as to be in pain or distress of any kind excites the most
excessive sorrow, so to conceive or to imagine that we are in it, excites
some degree of the same emotion, in proportion to the vivacity or
dulness of the conception.
That this is the source of our fellow-feeling for the misery of others,
that it is by changing places in fancy with the sufferer, that we come
either to conceive or to be affected by what he feels, may be demonstrated by many obvious observations, if it should not be thought sufficiently evident of itself. When we see a stroke aimed and just ready
to fall upon the leg or arm of another person, we naturally shrink
and draw back our own leg or our own arm; and when itdoes fall,
we feel itin some measure, and are hurtby itas well as the sufferer.
The mob, when they are gazing at a dancer on the slack rope, naturally writhe and twist and balance their own bodies, as they see him
do, and as they feel that they themselves must do if in his situation.
Persons of delicate fibres and a weak constitution of body complain,
that in looking on the sores and ulcers which are exposed by beggars
in the streets, they are apt to feel an itching or uneasy sensation in
the correspondent part of their own bodies. The horror which they
conceive at the misery of those wretches affects that particular part
in themselves more than any other; because that horror arises from
conceiving what they themselves would suffer, if they really were the
wretches whom they are looking upon, and if that particular part in
themselves was actually affected in the same miserable manner. The
very force of this conception is sufficient, in their feeble frames, to
produce that itching or uneasy sensation complained of. Men of the
most robust make, observe that in looking upon sore eyes they often
Cf. VII.iii..
Of the propriety of action
feel a very sensible soreness in their own, which proceeds from the
same reason; that organ being in the strongest man more delicate, than
any other part of the body is in the weakest.
Neither is it those circumstances only, which create pain or sorrow,
that call forth our fellow-feeling. Whatever is the passion which arises
from any objectin the person principally concerned, an analogous
emotion springs up, at the thought of his situation, in the breast of
every attentive spectator. Our joy for the deliverance of those heroes
of tragedy or romance who interest us, is as sincere as our grief for
their distress, and our fellow-feeling with their misery is not more real
than that with their happiness. We enter into their gratitude towards
those faithful friends who did not desert them in their difficulties; and
we heartily go along with their resentment against those perfidious
traitors who injured, abandoned, or deceived them. In every passion
of which the mind of man is susceptible, the emotions of the by-stander
always correspond to what, by bringing the case home to himself, he
imagines should be the sentiments of the sufferer.
Pity and compassion are words appropriated to signify our fellowfeeling with the sorrow of others. Sympathy, though its meaning was,
perhaps, originally the same, may now, however, without much impropriety, be made use of to denote our fellow-feeling with any passion
whatever.
Upon some occasions sympathy may seem to arise merely from the
view of a certain emotion in another person. The passions, upon some
occasions, may seem to be transfused from one man to another, instantaneously, and antecedent to any knowledge of what excited them in
the person principally concerned. Grief and joy, for example, strongly
expressed in the look and gestures of any one, at once affect the spectator with some degree of a like painful or agreeable emotion. A smiling
face is, to every body that sees it, a cheerful object; as a sorrowful
countenance, on the other hand, is a melancholy one.
This, however, does not hold universally, or with regard to every passion. There are some passions of which the expressions excite no sort
Cf. I.iii..
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
of sympathy, but before we are acquainted with what gave occasion to
them, serve rather to disgust and provoke us against them. The furious behaviour of an angry man is more likely to exasperate us against
himself than against his enemies. As we are unacquainted with his
provocation, we cannot bring his case home to ourselves, nor conceive
any thing like the passions which it excites. But we plainly see what
is the situation of those with whom he is angry, and to what violence
they may be exposed from so enraged an adversary. We readily, therefore, sympathize with their fear or resentment, and are immediately
disposed to take part against the man from whom they appear to be
in so much danger.
If the very appearances of grief and joy inspire us with some degree
of the like emotions, it is because they suggest to us the general idea
of some good or bad fortune that has befallen the person in whom
we observe them: and in these passions this is sufficient to have some
little influence upon us. The effects of grief and joy terminate in the
person who feels those emotions, of which the expressions do not, like
those of resentment, suggest to us the idea of any other person for
whom we are concerned, and whose interests are opposite to his. The
general idea of good or bad fortune, therefore, creates some concern for
the person who has met with it, but the general idea of provocation
excites no sympathy with the anger of the man who has received
it. Nature, it seems, teaches us to be more averse to enter into this
passion, and, tillinformed ofits cause, to be disposed rather to take part
againstit.
Even our sympathy with the grief or joy of another, before we are
informed of the cause of either, is always extremely imperfect. General
lamentations, which express nothing but the anguish of the sufferer,
create rather a curiosity to inquire into his situation, along with some
disposition to sympathize with him, than any actual sympathy that is
very sensible. The firstquestion which we ask is, Whathas befallen
you? Till this be answered, though we are uneasy both from the vague
idea of his misfortune, and still more from torturing ourselves with
Cf. I.ii..
Of the propriety of action
conjectures aboutwhatitmay be, yetour fellow-feeling is notvery
considerable.
Sympathy, therefore, does not arise so much from the view of the
passion, as from that of the situation which excites it. We sometimes
feel for another, a passion of which he himself seems to be altogether
incapable; because, when we putourselves in his case, thatpassion
arises in our breast from the imagination, though it does not in his
from the reality. We blush for the impudence and rudeness of another,
though he himself appears to have no sense of the impropriety of
his own behaviour; because we cannothelp feeling with whatconfusion we ourselves should be covered, had we behaved in so absurd a
manner.
Of all the calamities to which the condition of mortality exposes
mankind, the loss of reason appears, to those who have the least spark
of humanity, by far the most dreadful, and they behold that last stage
of human wretchedness with deeper commiseration than any other.
But the poor wretch, who is in it, laughs and sings perhaps, and is
altogether insensible of his own misery. The anguish which humanity
feels, therefore, at the sight of such an object, cannot be the reflection
of any sentiment of the sufferer. The compassion of the spectator must
arise altogether from the consideration of what he himself would feel
if he was reduced to the same unhappy situation, and, what perhaps
is impossible, was at the same time able to regard it with his present
reason and judgment.
What are the pangs of a mother, when she hears the moanings of her
infantthatduring the agony of disease cannotexpress whatitfeels?
In her idea of whatitsuffers, she joins, to its real helplessness, her
own consciousness of that helplessness, and her own terrors for the
unknown consequences of its disorder; and out of all these, forms, for
her own sorrow, the most complete image of misery and distress. The
infant, however, feels only the uneasiness of the present instant, which
can never be great. With regard to the future, it is perfectly secure,
and in its thoughtlessness and want of foresight, possesses an antidote
against fear and anxiety, the great tormentors of the human breast,
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
from which reason and philosophy will, in vain, attempt to defend it,
when itgrows up to a man.
We sympathize even with the dead, and overlooking what is of real
importance in their situation, that awful futurity which awaits them,
we are chiefly affected by those circumstances which strike our senses,
butcan have no influence upon their happiness. Itis miserable, we
think, to be deprived of the light of the sun; to be shut out from life
and conversation; to be laid in the cold grave, a prey to corruption and
the reptiles of the earth; to be no more thought of in this world, but
to be obliterated, in a little time, from the affections, and almost from
the memory, of their dearest friends and relations. Surely, we imagine,
we can never feel too much for those who have suffered so dreadful a
calamity. The tribute of our fellow-feeling seems doubly due to them
now, when they are in danger of being forgot by every body; and, by
the vain honours which we pay to their memory, we endeavour, for our
own misery, artificially to keep alive our melancholy remembrance of
their misfortune. That our sympathy can afford them no consolation
seems to be an addition to their calamity; and to think that all we can
do is unavailing, and that, what alleviates all other distress, the regret,
the love, and the lamentations of their friends, can yield no comfort
to them, serves only to exasperate our sense of their misery. The
happiness of the dead, however, most assuredly, is affected by none of
these circumstances; nor is it the thought of these things which can
ever disturb the profound security of their repose. The idea of that
dreary and endless melancholy, which the fancy naturally ascribes to
their condition, arises altogether from our joining to the change which
has been produced upon them, our own consciousness of that change,
from our putting ourselves in their situation, and from our lodging,
if I may be allowed to say so, our own living souls in their inanimated
bodies, and thence conceiving what would be our emotions in this
case. It is from this very illusion of the imagination, that the foresight
of our own dissolution is so terrible to us, and that the idea of those
circumstances, which undoubtedly can give us no pain when we are
dead, makes us miserable while we are alive. And from thence arises
one of the most important principles in human nature, the dread of
death, the great poison to the happiness, but the great restraint upon
Of the propriety of action
the injustice of mankind, which, while it afflicts and mortifies the
individual, guards and protects the society.
Chapter II Of the pleasure of mutual sympathy
But whatever may be the cause of sympathy, or however it may be
excited, nothing pleases us more than to observe in other men a fellowfeeling with all the emotions of our own breast; nor are we ever so much
shocked as by the appearance of the contrary. Those who are fond of
deducing all our sentiments from certain refinements of self-love, think
themselves at no loss to account, according to their own principles, both
for this pleasure and this pain. Man, say they, conscious of his own
weakness, and of the need which he has for the assistance of others,
rejoices whenever he observes that they adopt his own passions, because
he is then assured of that assistance; and grieves whenever he observes
the contrary, because he is then assured of their opposition. But both
the pleasure and the pain are always felt so instantaneously, and often
upon such frivolous occasions, thatitseems evidentthatneither of them
can be derived from any such self-interested consideration. A man is
mortified when, after having endeavoured to divert the company, he
looks round and sees that nobody laughs at his jests but himself. On
the contrary, the mirth of the company is highly agreeable to him, and
he regards this correspondence of their sentiments with his own as the
greatest applause.
Neither does his pleasure seem to arise altogether from the additional
vivacity which his mirth may receive from sympathy with theirs, nor
his pain from the disappointment he meets with when he misses this
pleasure; though both the one and the other, no doubt, do in some
measure. When we have read a book or poem so often that we can no
longer find any amusement in reading it by ourselves, we can still take
pleasure in reading it to a companion. To him it has all the graces of
novelty; we enter into the surprise and admiration which it naturally
Cf. Smith’s discussion of Bernard Mandeville in VII.ii. and of Thomas Hobbes in VII.iii.; and
compare Joseph Butler, Fifteen Sermons, V, and David Hume, Inquiry Concerning the Principles of
Morals, V.–, IX.–, and App. .
Cf. I.iii...
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
excites in him, butwhich itis no longer capable of exciting in us; we
consider all the ideas which it presents rather in the light in which
they appear to him, than in that in which they appear to ourselves, and
we are amused by sympathy with his amusement which thus enlivens
our own. On the contrary, we should be vexed if he did not seem to be
entertained with it, and we could no longer take any pleasure in reading
it to him. It is the same case here. The mirth of the company, no doubt,
enlivens our own mirth, and their silence, no doubt, disappoints us. But
though this may contribute both to the pleasure which we derive from
the one, and to the pain which we feel from the other, it is by no means
the sole cause of either; and this correspondence of the sentiments of
others with our own appears to be a cause of pleasure, and the want
of it a cause of pain, which cannot be accounted for in this manner.
The sympathy, which my friends express with my joy, might, indeed,
give me pleasure by enlivening thatjoy: butthatwhich they express
with my grief could give me none, if it served only to enliven that grief.
Sympathy, however, enlivens joy and alleviates grief. It enlivens joy
by presenting another source of satisfaction; and it alleviates grief by
insinuating into the heart almost the only agreeable sensation which it
is atthattime capable of receiving.
It is to be observed accordingly, that we are still more anxious to communicate to our friends our disagreeable than our agreeable passions,
that we derive still more satisfaction from their sympathy with the former than from that with the latter, and that we are still more shocked
by the want of it.
How are the unfortunate relieved when they have found out a person
to whom they can communicate the cause of their sorrow? Upon his
sympathy they seem to disburthen themselves of a part of their distress:
he is not improperly said to share it with them. He not only feels a
sorrow of the same kind with that which they feel, but as if he had
derived a part of it to himself, what he feels seems to alleviate the
weight of what they feel. Yet by relating their misfortunes they in
some measure renew their grief. They awaken in their memory the
remembrance of those circumstances which occasioned their affliction.
Their tears accordingly flow faster than before, and they are apt to
abandon themselves to all the weakness of sorrow. They take pleasure,
Of the propriety of action
however, in all this, and, it is evident, are sensibly relieved by it; because
the sweetness of his sympathy more than compensates the bitterness
of that sorrow, which, in order to excite this sympathy, they had thus
enlivened and renewed. The cruelest insult, on the contrary, which
can be offered to the unfortunate, is to appear to make light of their
calamities. To seem not to be affected with the joy of our companions
is but want of politeness; but not to wear a serious countenance when
they tell us their afflictions, is real and gross inhumanity.
Love is an agreeable; resentment, a disagreeable passion; and accordingly we are nothalf so anxious thatour friends should adoptour
friendships, as that they should enter into our resentments. We can
forgive them though they seem to be little affected with the favours
which we may have received, but lose all patience if they seem indifferent about the injuries which may have been done to us: nor are we
half so angry with them for not entering into our gratitude, as for not
sympathizing with our resentment. They can easily avoid being friends
to our friends, but can hardly avoid being enemies to those with whom
we are at variance. We seldom resent their being at enmity with the
first, though upon that account we may sometimes affect to make an
awkward quarrel with them; but we quarrel with them in good earnest
if they live in friendship with the last. The agreeable passions of love
and joy can satisfy and support the heart without any auxiliary pleasure.
The bitter and painful emotions of grief and resentment more strongly
require the healing consolation of sympathy.
As the person who is principally interested in any event is pleased
with our sympathy, and hurt by the want of it, so we, too, seem to
be pleased when we are able to sympathize with him, and to be hurt
when we are unable to do so. We run not only to congratulate the
successful, but to condole with the afflicted; and the pleasure which we
find in the conversation of one whom in all the passions of his heart
we can entirely sympathize with, seems to do more than compensate the
painfulness of that sorrow with which the view of his situation affects
us. On the contrary, it is always disagreeable to feel that we cannot
sympathize with him, and instead of being pleased with this exemption
from sympathetic pain, it hurts us to find that we cannot share his
uneasiness. If we hear a person loudly lamenting his misfortunes, which
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
however, upon bringing the case home to ourselves, we feel, can produce
no such violenteffectupon us, we are shocked athis grief; and, because
we cannot enter into it, call it pusillanimity and weakness. It gives us
the spleen, on the other hand, to see another too happy or too much
elevated, as we call it, with any little piece of good fortune. We are
disobliged even with his joy; and, because we cannot go along with it,
call itlevity and folly. We are even putoutof humour if our companion
laughs louder or longer at a joke than we think it deserves; that is, than
we feel that we ourselves could laugh at it.
Chapter III Of the manner in which we judge of the propriety
or impropriety of the affections of other men, by their concord
or dissonance with our own
When the original passions of the person principally concerned are in
perfect concord with the sympathetic emotions of the spectator, they
necessarily appear to this last just and proper, and suitable to their
objects; and, on the contrary, when, upon bringing the case home to
himself, he finds that they do not coincide with what he feels, they
necessarily appear to him unjust and improper, and unsuitable to the
causes which excite them. To approve of the passions of another,
therefore, as suitable to their objects, is the same thing as to observe
that we entirely sympathize with them; and not to approve of them as
such, is the same thing as to observe that we do not entirely sympathize
with them. The man who resents the injuries that have been done to
me, and observes that I resent them precisely as he does, necessarily
approves of my resentment. The man whose sympathy keeps time
to my grief, cannotbutadmitthe reasonableness of my sorrow. He
who admires the same poem, or the same picture, and admires them
exactly as I do, must surely allow the justness of my admiration. He
who laughs at the same joke, and laughs along with me, cannot well
deny the propriety of my laughter. On the contrary, the person who,
upon these different occasions, either feels no such emotion as that
which I feel, or feels none that bears any proportion to mine, cannot
avoid disapproving my sentiments on account of their dissonance with
his own. If my animosity goes beyond what the indignation of my
friend can correspond to; if my grief exceeds what his most tender
compassion can go along with; if my admiration is either too high or
Of the propriety of action
too low to tally with his own; if I laugh loud and heartily when he
only smiles, or, on the contrary, only smile when he laughs loud and
heartily; in all these cases, as soon as he comes from considering the
object, to observe how I am affected by it, according as there is more
or less disproportion between his sentiments and mine, I must incur a
greater or less degree of his disapprobation: and upon all occasions his
own sentiments are the standards and measures by which he judges
of mine.
To approve of another man’s opinions is to adopt those opinions,
and to adopt them is to approve of them. If the same arguments
which convince you convince me likewise, I necessarily approve of
your conviction; and if they do not, I necessarily disapprove of it:
neither can I possibly conceive that I should do the one without the
other. To approve or disapprove, therefore, of the opinions of others is
acknowledged, by every body, to mean no more than to observe their
agreement or disagreement with our own. But this is equally the case
with regard to our approbation or disapprobation of the sentiments
or passions of others.
There are, indeed, some cases in which we seem to approve without
any sympathy or correspondence of sentiments, and in which, consequently, the sentiment of approbation would seem to be different
from the perception of this coincidence. A little attention, however,
will convince us that even in these cases our approbation is ultimately
founded upon a sympathy or correspondence of this kind. I shall give
an instance in things of a very frivolous nature, because in them the
judgments of mankind are less apt to be perverted by wrong systems.
We may often approve of a jest, and think the laughter of the company
quite just and proper, though we ourselves do not laugh, because,
perhaps, we are in a grave humour, or happen to have our attention
engaged with other objects. We have learned, however, from experience, whatsortof pleasantry is upon mostoccasions capable of making
us laugh, and we observe that this is one of that kind. We approve,
therefore, of the laughter of the company, and feel that it is natural
and suitable to its object; because, though in our present mood we
cannot easily enter into it, we are sensible that upon most occasions
we should very heartily join in it.
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
The same thing often happens with regard to all the other passions.
A stranger passes by us in the street with all the marks of the deepest
affliction; and we are immediately told that he has just received the
news of the death of his father. It is impossible that, in this case, we
should notapprove of his grief. Yetitmay often happen, withoutany
defect of humanity on our part, that, so far from entering into the
violence of his sorrow, we should scarce conceive the first movements
of concern upon his account. Both he and his father, perhaps, are entirely unknown to us, or we happen to be employed about other things,
and do not take time to picture out in our imagination the different
circumstances of distress which must occur to him. We have learned,
however, from experience, that such a misfortune naturally excites
such a degree of sorrow, and we know that if we took time to consider
his situation, fully and in all its parts, we should, without doubt, most
sincerely sympathize with him. It is upon the consciousness of this
conditional sympathy, that our approbation of his sorrow is founded,
even in those cases in which that sympathy does not actually take
place; and the general rules derived from our preceding experience of
what our sentiments would commonly correspond with, correct upon
this, as upon many other occasions, the impropriety of our present
emotions.
The sentiment or affection of the heart from which any action proceeds, and upon which its whole virtue or vice must ultimately depend,
may be considered under two different aspects, or in two different relations; first, in relation to the cause which excites it, or the motive
which gives occasion to it; and secondly, in relation to the end which
it proposes, or the effect which it tends to produce.
In the suitableness or unsuitableness, in the proportion or disproportion which the affection seems to bear to the cause or object which
excites it, consists the propriety or impropriety, the decency or ungracefulness of the consequent action.
In the beneficial or hurtful nature of the effects which the affection
aims at, or tends to produce, consists the merit or demerit of the
action, the qualities by which it is entitled to reward, or is deserving
of punishment.
Of the propriety of action
Philosophers have, of late years, considered chiefly the tendency of
affections, and have given little attention to the relation which they
stand in to the cause which excites them. In common life, however,
when we judge of any person’s conduct, and of the sentiments which
directed it, we constantly consider them under both these aspects.
When we blame in another man the excesses of love, of grief, of resentment, we not only consider the ruinous effects which they tend
to produce, but the little occasion which was given for them. The
merit of his favourite, we say, is not so great, his misfortune is not
so dreadful, his provocation is not so extraordinary, as to justify so
violenta passion. We should have indulged, we say; perhaps, have
approved of the violence of his emotion, had the cause been in any
respect proportioned to it.
When we judge in this manner of any affection, as proportioned or
disproportioned to the cause which excites it, it is scarce possible that
we should make use of any other rule or canon but the correspondent
affection in ourselves. If, upon bringing the case home to our own
breast, we find that the sentiments which it gives occasion to, coincide
and tallywith our own,we necessarily approve of them as proportioned
and suitable to their objects; if otherwise, we necessarily disapprove
of them, as extravagant and out of proportion.
Every faculty in one man is the measure by which he judges of the
like faculty in another. I judge of your sight by my sight, of your ear
by my ear, of your reason by my reason, of your resentment by my
resentment, of your love by my love. I neither have, nor can have, any
other way of judging about them.
Chapter IV The same subject continued
We may judge of the propriety or impropriety of the sentiments of
another person by their correspondence or disagreement with our
own, upon two different occasions; either, first,when the objectswhich
excite them are considered without any peculiar relation, either to
ourselves or to the person whose sentiments we judge of; or, secondly,
when they are considered as peculiarly affecting one or other of us.
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
I With regard to those objects which are considered without any peculiar relation either to ourselves or to the person whose sentiments
we judge of; wherever his sentiments entirely correspond with our
own, we ascribe to him the qualities of taste and good judgment. The
beauty of a plain, the greatness of a mountain, the ornaments of a
building, the expression of a picture, the composition of a discourse,
the conduct of a third person, the proportions of different quantities
and numbers, the various appearances which the great machine of the
universe is perpetually exhibiting, with the secret wheels and springs
which produce them; all the general subjects of science and taste, are
whatwe and our companion regard as having no peculiar relation
to either of us. We both look at them from the same point of view,
and we have no occasion for sympathy, or for that imaginary change
of situations from which it arises, in order to produce, with regard
to these, the most perfect harmony of sentiments and affections. If,
notwithstanding, we are often differently affected, it arises either from
the different degrees of attention, which our different habits of life
allow us to give easily to the several parts of those complex objects, or
from the different degrees of natural acuteness in the faculty of the
mind to which they are addressed.
When the sentiments of our companion coincide with our own in
things of this kind, which are obvious and easy, and in which, perhaps, we never found a single person who differed from us, though
we, no doubt, must approve of them, yet he seems to deserve no praise
or admiration on account of them. But when they not only coincide
with our own, butlead and directour own; when in forming them he
appears to have attended to many things which we had overlooked, and
to have adjusted them to all the various circumstances of their objects;
we notonly approve of them, butwonder and are surprised attheir
uncommon and unexpected acuteness and comprehensiveness, and
he appears to deserve a very high degree of admiration and applause.
For approbation heightened by wonder and surprise, constitutes the
sentiment which is properly called admiration, and of which applause
is the natural expression. The decision of the man who judges that
Cf. I.ii..; and concerning the general role of wonder and surprise in human knowledge, see
‘History of Astronomy’, I–II (in EPS).
Of the propriety of action
exquisite beauty is preferable to the grossest deformity, or that twice
two are equal to four, must certainly be approved of by all the world,
but will not, surely, be much admired. It is the acute and delicate
discernment of the man of taste, who distinguishes the minute, and
scarce perceptible differences of beauty and deformity; it is the comprehensive accuracy of the experienced mathematician, who unravels,
with ease, the most intricate and perplexed proportions; it is the great
leader in science and taste, the man who directs and conducts our own
sentiments, the extent and superior justness of whose talents astonish
us with wonder and surprise, who excites our admiration, and seems
to deserve our applause: and upon this foundation is grounded the
greater part of the praise which is bestowed upon what are called the
intellectual virtues.
The utility of those qualities, it may be thought, is what first recommends them to us; and, no doubt, the consideration of this, when we
come to attend to it, gives them a new value. Originally, however, we
approve of another man’s judgment, not as something useful, but as
right, as accurate, as agreeable to truth and reality: and it is evident we
attribute those qualities to it for no other reason but because we find
that it agrees with our own. Taste, in the same manner, is originally
approved of, not as useful, but as just, as delicate, and as precisely
suited to its object. The idea of the utility of all qualities of this kind,
is plainly an after-thought, and not what first recommends them to
our approbation.
II With regard to those objects, which affect in a particular manner
either ourselves or the person whose sentiments we judge of, it is at
once more difficult to preserve this harmony and correspondence,
and at the same time, vastly more important. My companion does not
naturally look upon the misfortune that has befallen me, or the injury
that has been done me, from the same point of view in which I consider
them. They affect me much more nearly.We do not view them from the
same station, as we do a picture, or a poem, or a system of philosophy,
and are, therefore, apt to be very differently affected by them. But
I can much more easily overlook the want of this correspondence of
Cf. the discussion of Hume at IV.ii.–.
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
sentiments with regard to such indifferent objects as concern neither
me nor my companion, than with regard to what interests me so
much as the misfortune that has befallen me, or the injury that has
been done me. Though you despise that picture, or that poem, or
even that system of philosophy, which I admire, there is little danger
of our quarrelling upon that account. Neither of us can reasonably be
much interested about them. They ought all of them to be matters
of great indifference to us both; so that, though our opinions may
be opposite, our affections may still be very nearly the same. But it
is quite otherwise with regard to those objects by which either you
or I are particularly affected. Though your judgments in matters of
speculation, though your sentiments in matters of taste, are quite
opposite to mine, I can easily overlook this opposition; and if I have
any degree of temper, I may still find some entertainment in your
conversation, even upon those very subjects. But if you have either no
fellow-feeling for the misfortunes I have met with, or none that bears
any proportion to the grief which distracts me; or if you have either
no indignation at the injuries I have suffered, or none that bears any
proportion to the resentment which transports me, we can no longer
converse upon these subjects. We become intolerable to one another. I
can neither support your company, nor you mine. You are confounded
atmy violence and passion, and I am enraged atyour cold insensibility
and wantof feeling.
In all such cases, that there may be some correspondence of sentiments between the spectator and the person principally concerned,
the spectator must, first of all, endeavour, as much as he can, to put
himself in the situation of the other, and to bring home to himself
every little circumstance of distress which can possibly occur to the
sufferer. He must adopt the whole case of his companion with all its
minutest incidents; and strive to render as perfect as possible, that
imaginary change of situation upon which his sympathy is founded.
After all this, however, the emotions of the spectator will still be
very apt to fall short of the violence of what is felt by the sufferer.
Mankind, though naturally sympathetic, never conceive, for what has
befallen another, that degree of passion which naturally animates the
Of the propriety of action
person principally concerned. That imaginary change of situation,
uponwhich their sympathyis founded,is butmomentary. The thought
of their own safety, the thought that they themselves are not really the
sufferers, continually intrudes itself upon them; and though it does
not hinder them from conceiving a passion somewhat analogous to
what is felt by the sufferer, hinders them from conceiving any thing
that approaches to the same degree of violence. The person principally
concerned is sensible of this, and at the same time passionately desires
a more complete sympathy. He longs for that relief which nothing can
afford him but the entire concord of the affections of the spectators
with his own. To see the emotions of their hearts, in every respect,
beat time to his own, in the violent and disagreeable passions, constitutes his sole consolation. But he can only hope to obtain this by
lowering his passion to that pitch, in which the spectators are capable
of going along with him. He must flatten, if I may be allowed to say so,
the sharpness of its natural tone, in order to reduce it to harmony and
concord with the emotions of those who are about him.What they feel,
will, indeed, always be, in some respects, different from what he feels,
and compassion can never be exactly the same with original sorrow;
because the secret consciousness that the change of situations, from
which the sympathetic sentiment arises, is but imaginary, not only
lowers itin degree, but, in some measure, varies itin kind, and gives it
a quite different modification. These two sentiments, however, may,
it is evident, have such a correspondence with one another, as is sufficient for the harmony of society. Though they will never be unisons,
they may be concords, and this is all that is wanted or required.
In order to produce this concord, as nature teaches the spectators to
assume the circumstances of the person principally concerned, so she
teaches this last in some measure to assume those of the spectators. As
they are continually placing themselves in his situation, and thence
conceiving emotions similar to what he feels; so he is as constantly
placing himself in theirs, and thence conceiving some degree of that
coolness about his own fortune, with which he is sensible that they
will view it. As they are constantly considering what they themselves
would feel, if they actually were the sufferers, so he is as constantly led
to imagine in what manner he would be affected if he was only one of
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
the spectators of his own situation. As their sympathy makes them look
at it, in some measure, with his eyes, so his sympathy makes him look
at it, in some measure, with theirs, especially when in their presence
and acting under their observation: and as the reflected passion, which
he thus conceives, is much weaker than the original one, it necessarily
abates the violence of what he felt before he came into their presence,
before he began to recollect in what manner they would be affected
by it, and to view his situation in this candid and impartial light.
The mind, therefore, is rarely so disturbed, but that the company of
a friend will restore it to some degree of tranquillity and sedateness.
The breastis, in some measure, calmed and composed the momentwe
come into his presence. We are immediately put in mind of the light in
which he will view our situation, and we begin to view it ourselves in
the same light; for the effect of sympathy is instantaneous. We expect
less sympathy from a common acquaintance than from a friend: we
cannot open to the former all those little circumstances which we can
unfold to the latter: we assume, therefore, more tranquillity before
him, and endeavour to fix our thoughts upon those general outlines
of our situation which he is willing to consider. We expect still less
sympathy from an assembly of strangers, and we assume, therefore,
still more tranquillity before them, and always endeavour to bring
down our passion to that pitch, which the particular company we are
in may be expected to go along with. Nor is this only an assumed
appearance: for if we are at all masters of ourselves, the presence of
a mere acquaintance will really compose us, still more than that of a
friend; and that of an assembly of strangers still more than that of an
acquaintance.
Society and conversation, therefore, are the most powerful remedies
for restoring the mind to its tranquillity, if, at any time, it has unfortunately lost it; as well as the best preservatives of that equal and happy
temper, which is so necessary to self-satisfaction and enjoyment. Men
of retirement and speculation, who are apt to sit brooding at home
over either grief or resentment, though they may often have more
humanity, more generosity, and a nicer sense of honour, yet seldom
possess that equality of temper which is so common among men of the
world.
Of the propriety of action
Chapter V Of the amiable and respectable virtues
Upon these two different efforts, upon that of the spectator to enter
into the sentiments of the person principally concerned, and upon
that of the person principally concerned, to bring down his emotions
to what the spectator can go along with, are founded two different
sets of virtues. The soft, the gentle, the amiable virtues, the virtues of
candid condescension and indulgent humanity, are founded upon the
one: the great, the awful and respectable, the virtues of self-denial, of
self-government, of that command of the passions which subjects all
the movements of our nature to what our own dignity and honour,
and the propriety of our own conduct require, take their origin from
the other.
How amiable does he appear to be, whose sympathetic heart seems
to re-echo all the sentiments of those with whom he converses, who
grieves for their calamities, who resents their injuries, and who rejoices
at their good fortune! When we bring home to ourselves the situation
of his companions, we enter into their gratitude, and feel what consolation they must derive from the tender sympathy of so affectionate
a friend. And for a contrary reason, how disagreeable does he appear
to be, whose hard and obdurate heart feels for himself only, but is
altogether insensible to the happiness or misery of others! We enter,
in this case too, into the pain which his presence must give to every
mortal with whom he converses, to those especially with whom we are
most apt to sympathize, the unfortunate and the injured.
On the other hand, what noble propriety and grace do we feel in
the conduct of those who, in their own case, exert that recollection
and self-command which constitute the dignity of every passion, and
which bring it down to what others can enter into! We are disgusted
with that clamorous grief, which, without any delicacy, calls upon our
compassion with sighs and tears and importunate lamentations. But
we reverence thatreserved, thatsilentand majestic sorrow, which
discovers itself only in the swelling of the eyes, in the quivering of
the lips and cheeks, and in the distant, but affecting, coldness of the
whole behaviour. Itimposes the like silence upon us. We regard itwith
Cf. III.iii.; VII.ii.–; and Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, III.iii.; Inquiry, App. ..
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
respectful attention, and watch with anxious concern over our whole
behaviour, lest by any impropriety we should disturb that concerted
tranquillity, which it requires so great an effort to support.
The insolence and brutality of anger, in the same manner, when we
indulge its fury without check or restraint, is, of all objects, the most
detestable. But we admire that noble and generous resentment which
governs its pursuit of the greatest injuries, not by the rage which they
are apt to excite in the breast of the sufferer, but by the indignation
which they naturally call forth in that of the impartial spectator; which
allows no word, no gesture, to escape it beyond what this more equitable sentiment would dictate; which never, even in thought, attempts
any greater vengeance, nor desires to inflict any greater punishment,
than what every indifferent person would rejoice to see executed.
And hence it is, that to feel much for others and little for ourselves,
that to restrain our selfish, and to indulge our benevolent affections,
constitutes the perfection of human nature; and can alone produce
among mankind that harmony of sentiments and passions in which
consists their whole grace and propriety. As to love our neighbour
as we love ourselves is the great law of Christianity, so it is the great
precept of nature to love ourselves only as we love our neighbour, or
what comes to the same thing, as our neighbour is capable of loving us.
As taste and good judgment, when they are considered as qualities
which deserve praise and admiration, are supposed to imply a delicacy of sentiment and an acuteness of understanding not commonly
to be met with; so the virtues of sensibility and self-command are not
apprehended to consist in the ordinary, but in the uncommon degrees
of those qualities. The amiable virtue of humanity requires, surely,
a sensibility, much beyond what is possessed by the rude vulgar of
mankind. The great and exalted virtue of magnanimity undoubtedly
demands much more than that degree of self-command, which the
weakest of mortals is capable of exerting. As in the common degree
of the intellectual qualities, there is no abilities; so in the common
degree of the moral, there is no virtue. Virtue is excellence, something
uncommonly greatand beautiful, which rises far above whatis vulgar
Cf. III.vi..
Of the propriety of action
and ordinary. The amiable virtues consist in that degree of sensibility
which surprises by its exquisite and unexpected delicacy and tenderness. The awful and respectable, in that degree of self-command
which astonishes by its amazing superiority over the most ungovernable passions of human nature.
There is, in this respect, a considerable difference between virtue and
mere propriety; between those qualities and actions which deserve
to be admired and celebrated, and those which simply deserve to be
approved of. Upon many occasions, to act with the most perfect propriety, requires no more than that common and ordinary degree of
sensibility or self-command which the most worthless of mankind are
possest of, and sometimes even that degree is not necessary. Thus,
to give a very low instance, to eat when we are hungry, is certainly,
upon ordinary occasions, perfectly rightand proper, and cannotmiss
being approved of as such by every body. Nothing, however, could be
more absurd than to say it was virtuous.
On the contrary, there may frequently be a considerable degree of
virtue in those actions which fall short of the most perfect propriety;
because they may still approach nearer to perfection than could well
be expected upon occasions in which it was so extremely difficult to
attain it: and this is very often the case upon those occasions which
require the greatest exertions of self-command. There are some situations which bear so hard upon human nature, that the greatest degree
of self-government, which can belong to so imperfect a creature as
man, is not able to stifle, altogether, the voice of human weakness, or
reduce the violence of the passions to that pitch of moderation, in
which the impartial spectator can entirely enter into them. Though
in those cases, therefore, the behaviour of the sufferer fall short of the
mostperfectpropriety, itmay still deserve some applause, and even in
a certain sense, may be denominated virtuous. It may still manifest an
effort of generosity and magnanimity of which the greater part of men
are incapable; and though it fails of absolute perfection, it may be a
much nearer approximation towards perfection, than what, upon such
trying occasions, is commonly either to be found or to be expected.
Cf. VII.ii..
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
In cases of this kind, when we are determining the degree of blame or
applause which seems due to any action, we very frequently make use
of two different standards. The first is the idea of complete propriety
and perfection, which, in those difficult situations, no human conduct
ever did, or ever can come up to; and in comparison with which the
actions of all men must for ever appear blameable and imperfect. The
second is the idea of that degree of proximity or distance from this
complete perfection, which the actions of the greater part of men commonly arrive at. Whatever goes beyond this degree, how far soever it
may be removed from absolute perfection, seems to deserve applause;
and whatever falls short of it, to deserve blame.
It is in the same manner that we judge of the productions of all the arts
which address themselves to the imagination. When a critic examines
thework of any of the great masters in poetry or painting, he may sometimes examine it by an idea of perfection, in his own mind, which neither that nor any other human work will ever come up to; and as long as
he compares it with this standard, he can see nothing in it but faults and
imperfections. But when he comes to consider the rank which it ought
to hold among other works of the same kind, he necessarily compares it
with a very different standard, the common degree of excellence which
is usually attained in this particular art; and when he judges of it by
this new measure, it may often appear to deserve the highest applause,
upon account of its approaching much nearer to perfection than the
greater part of those works which can be brought into competition
with it.
Comments
Post a Comment