tooze on eagleton
Terry Eagleton in earnest? The nagging
question is stirred in the reader’s mind by
the very first sentence of the very first
page of Why Marx Was Right. “This book had
its origin in a single, striking thought”, Eagleton tells us, “What if all the most familiar
objections to Marx’s work are mistaken? Or at
least, if not totally wrongheaded, mostly so?”
Are we supposed to ignore the tongue in
Eagleton’s cheek? His political commitments
are the stuff of well-honed legend. Readers of
his memoir, The Gatekeeper (2002), can make
an educated guess as to the place and time
at which this “striking thought” first struck
Eagleton: Cambridge in the early 1960s.
That’s almost fifty years and over forty books
ago. Moreover, the question by now defines
an entire genre. Jacques Derrida’s Spectres
of Marx, Meghnad Desai’s Marx’s Revenge,
Slavoj Zizek’s reissue of classic texts by Trotsky and Mao, Alain Badiou’s The Communist
Hypothesis all state the case.
The suspicion that Eagleton is pandering to
a notionally naive readership is confirmed by
the casualness with which he announces that
his text will consist of ten wrong-headed
ideas attributed to Marx, which he will rebut
in “no particular order of importance”. This
is not, we are clearly meant to understand,
anything as uncool as a systematic critique of
Marx or Marxism. The first two chapters – on
the supposed obsolescence of Marxism and
on Marxism as unfreedom – and the last four
chapters of the book – on class politics, on
violence, on the State and on “new social
movements” – more than deliver on this lowbrow promise. The examples are up to date –
Stalinism was like the internet dropped into
the Middle Ages. The language is crude. “To
go [sic] socialist, you need to be reasonably
well-heeled”. The Russian peasantry in the
late 1920s were analogous to a “premodern
tribe” confronted with capitalist management
consultants – presumably because on a stadial theory of social development, McKinsey
is to premodern tribe as Stalinist collectivizer
is to Ukrainian peasant. Since Stalinist violence was the result of backwardness, if true
socialism “took over in the Home Counties”,
only an “unusually bold-faced” sceptic
would ever expect “labour camps in Dorking”. We are in the world of the Idiot’s not
the Young Person’s Guide.
Chapters Three to Six, however – on determinism, utopia, economism and materialism –
could be said to redeem the book. Here
the knockabout language is toned down and
Eagleton develops a version of Marxism that
is consistent with his other well-documented
commitments. What Eagleton distils out of
Marx is a “philosophical anthropology”, a
view of our collective human nature on which
to found a social and political theory and
a vision of history. As individuated human
beings we have in common our needy,
labouring, sociable, sexual, communicative,
selfexpressive animal bodies. “Human consciousness ...is corporeal... it is ...a sign of
the way in which the body is always in a sense
unfinished, open-ended, always capable of
more creative activity . . .”. Change “is not the
opposite of human nature”, Eagleton insists:
“it is possible because of the creative, openended, unfinished beings we are”. What drives
history are the struggles individually and collectively to satisfy those needs. All hitherto
existing history, or rather, in Marxian terms,
pre-History, has about it the quality of compulsive, deterministic, forced motion precisely
because of the impossibility under current conditions of reconciling individual needs collectively. But this oppressive, tragic reality is a
spur to action. “There seems to be something
in humanity which will not bow meekly to the
insolence of power.” As Eagleton puts it in the
most lyrical lines of the book: “Tragedy is not
necessarily without hope. It is rather that when
it affirms, it does so in fear and trembling,
with a horror-stricken countenance”. Even
if they haven’t read Eagleton’s recent book
Reason, Faith, and Revolution (2009), some
sensitive readers may thrill to the religious
overtones in such passages. They may also be
tempted to jump to the obvious conclusion:
Professor Eagleton clearly believes that Karl
Marx captured the truth about human nature.
Socialism is the social and political system
that best conforms to that nature. So why not
simply reboot and rebuild society from those
natural foundations up? Indeed, Eagleton himself teeters on the edge of that anti-historical
vision in a tell-tale coda to Chapter Three:
“Suppose a handful of us were to crawl out of
the other side of a nuclear or environmental
cataclysm, and begin the daunting task of
building civilization again from scratch.
Given what we know of the causes of the catastrophe, would we not be well-advised to try it
this time the socialist way?”.
But Eagleton knows better than to tarry too
long with such 1980s dystopias. He knows
he has history to deal with. Indeed, historians
could do worse than to read the central theoretical sections of this book, as they should Eagleton’s essays collected in The Illusions of Postmodernism (1996). They provide a far more
intelligent commentary on what was at stake
in postmodernism’s attack on capital H
history than was ever provided by the discipline’s self-appointed guardians. But if history
or, rather, the ugly development of pre-history
is as critical as Eagleton knows it to be, then
he owes us at least a sketch map of how we get
from Marx’s texts in the 1840s to the present.
Indeed, Eagleton owes us two histories.
First of all, there is the problem of intellectual history. To derive a philosophical anthropology from the early Marx is certainly possible. But the intellectual project did not stop
there. Why opt for this 1840s philosophical
anthropology as opposed to other, later
versions? Eagleton makes shy references to
Nietzsche and even to Heidegger. He knows
that his account of situated subjectivity could
be read as akin to theirs. But the question of
why their philosophical anthropologies lead
them to political conclusions that Eagleton
obviously finds distasteful is not among his
chosen ten. If they are beyond the pale, what
of other schools that developed closely related
accounts of human agency and cognition?
What about pragmatism, with its distinctive
regional lineage from the St Louis Hegelians
to the University of Chicago? Eagleton has
no truck with Richard Rorty. He was under
the influence of the later Germans. But what
of John Dewey or George Herbert Mead?
Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir’s
accounts of the human condition star on any
Western Civ course. Slightly further off the
beaten track, how does Eagleton stand in relation to more recent German thinkers of a leftist
persuasion? Jürgen Habermas, Axel Honneth
and Hans Joas all explored the question of
how to found a radical politics on a philosophical anthropology. By the early 1970s, they
were convinced that to do so one had to escape
the confines of Marx’s rereading of Ludwig
Feuerbach.
But is all this too po-faced? Eagleton’s ultimate justification for singling out Marx as a
source of inspiration is rather different. It is
the history of modern politics. As he puts it
with suitable bluntness, there have never been
“Cartesian governments, Platonist guerrilla
fighters or Hegelian trade unions”. Marxism
was once a powerful political force. But that
answer merely faces Eagleton with even more
problems. He now has to explain how those
sympathetic to his brand of Marxian philosophical anthropology have actually related to
the tortured history of Marxist politics in the
twentieth century. How, for instance, does
Eagleton place himself in relation to Maurice
Merleau-Ponty, the French existentialist
whose account of human existence he clearly
finds sympathetic? In 1947, Merleau-Ponty
published Humanism and Terror, a remarkable meditation on the Stalinist terror. A few
years later, faced with fresh and compelling
evidence, Merleau-Ponty concluded that as a
project of emancipation Communism had
failed. Eagleton frequently invokes Theodor
Adorno and Walter Benjamin. But as Eagleton
knows, the Frankfurt School saw the violence
of modernity as posing profound intellectual
problems for Marxism. They came to see
Marx’s stress on human labour as dangerously
complicit with coercive reality.
Whereas Merleau-Ponty and the Frankfurt
School agreed in thinking that twentiethcentury history called into question philosophical foundations derived from the midnineteenth century, Eagleton keeps the
two neatly separated. He blithely expands the
concepts of labour and production to include
virtually every facet of self-realization. Meanwhile, the problem of Stalinist violence is
simply waved aside. “To judge socialism by
its results” in the Soviet Union, Eagleton
remarks, “would be like drawing conclusions
about the human race from a study of psychopaths in Kalamazoo”. Apparently, life in industrial Michigan will drive one to bedlam as
surely as Russian backwardness, and Stalin’s
cruelty barbarized Soviet Communism. This is
British barroom Trotskyism at its laziest. As
so often, Lenin escapes unscathed. “One of the
first decrees of the Bolsheviks when they
came to power”, Eagleton announces with misleading glibness, “was to abolish the death penalty.” “When the Soviet system fell”, it
collapsed “without much more [sic] bloodshed
than had occurred on the day of its foundation.” Does Eagleton not see the gross distortions involved in such throwaway lines?
Surely there is no need to rehearse the escalation of violence from the liberal reformist
politics of the February revolution of 1917 –
the people who actually deserve credit for first
abolishing the Tsar’s brutal penal regime – to
the lethal violence of Leninism? Zizek does
not stoop to this kind of evasion. The shock
effect of Lenin’s unapologetic calls for violence and dictatorship is precisely what he revels in. Alain Badiou for his part acknowledges
that if one is serious about restating the Communist hypothesis, one must begin with a meditation on failure rather than a self-righteous
assertion of why Marx was right. But then,
hard as it may be to credit, Badiou is in earnest
about his politics. Even in a text as sloppy as
this, Eagleton’s commitment to his personal
vision and humanist view is palpable. But is
politics really what is at stake here? For generations of serious-minded predecessors, a
philosophical anthropology much like that
espoused by Eagleton led to various brands of
reformist democratic politics. But for such
people – militant young leftists matured into
sceptical liberals – Terry Eagleton has only
scorn. As he boasts in his memoir, “sheer
horror of the cliché ...has preserved me from
this fashionable fate”. He need not worry.
His blustering concoction of Marxist literary
humanism, crude class politics and pub
humour is a personal brand all of his own.
Comments
Post a Comment